I recently read Anton Ford's paper The Province of Human Agency,
which recently appeared in Νοῦς (the third number of its
fifty-second volume), and it was a bit of an odd experience in that I
am extremely sympathetic to (what I take to be) the basic perspective
from which he writes, and the basic position he's trying to advocate
for (and I really liked his dissertation), but also (and I have this
experience a lot with let's call them Pittsburgh Anscombians) I found
the paper itself to be frustratingly hard to get a handle on. (I also
had the somewhat melancholy thought that my papers dammit would have
been relevant to its composition and its successors, should there be
any: here is someone, Ford, who would probably be interested in my
stuff! And might even have had cause to read some had I remained in
the academy, and conferred, and whatnot, but who now will, basically,
not.) But it was also somewhat annoying because I thought the use made
of Brian O'Shaughnessy was very shabby. I thought I would write a
short post substantiating that thought. I may or may not have
succeeded in substantiating it; I definitely failed in writing a short
post, or one that confines itself to that task.
Here's the context. A picture of action theory is given in which two
views do combat: volitionalism, in which all we ever do, sensu
stricto, is will, or intend, or try (in some purely mental sense of
"try"!), and what Ford calls, identifying it with the mainstream,
"corporealism", in which all we ever do is move our bodies, in some
sense which is unfortunately not laid out particularly clearly.
Davidson, for instance, explicitly endorses this view … or something
like it. (The view Davidson explicitly endorses is also not
particularly clear, so that fits, at least!) The immediate unclarity
is perhaps harmless, since Ford will later extend it to encompass one
which explicitly has it that we do do more than merely move our
bodies (Feinberg's, on p 712): the essential point for corporealism
isn't that the limit of our as we might put it contributions as
agents to what happens stops at the body, but that it stops
somewhere short of what happens. (As is also true of volitionalism.)
After some point, what we do is over, and the rest is just the
workings-out of cause and effect ("up to nature", in Davidson's
phrase), and (therefore) not what we do. Of course philosophers who
speak in such a way are willing to countenance what is apparently an
inexact habit of speech in which those effects do count as what we
do, by, I suppose, courtesy. Ford: they "uniformly go on to say that,
given the right setting and a certain amount of luck, moving one's
body might amount to something as sophisticated as turning on the
lights" (697), owing to the possibility of redescribing a cause in
terms of its effects (the famous "accordion effect"). But this is,
apparently, if we are to be rigorously philosophical, loose talk.
(Mark that luck, though!) Or such is, roughly, how Ford sets it out.
Given, then, that the issue is not really just about moving one's body
and what it might mean to say that all we ever do (in some privileged
sense) is that, the failure to get clear on what "all we ever do is
move our body" is perhaps excusable. Really, we are interested in the
idea that all we ever do (in some privileged sense) is less than
everything that happens when we do what we do (in that privileged
sense). But that doesn't remove the fundamental issue, which is that
we don't, yet, know what that privileged sense is! As a result of
which we don't know, for instance, how much of a courtesy the
extension of the title of deeds to those things which a person's
privileged deeds cause is. Maybe not much!
More of that later, though.
In order, then, to produce conviction in the reader that corporealism
is rampant, and found among partisans of numerous philosophical
orientations (not merely among those with scientistic or physicalist
sympathies), we get a brief list, with one or two supporting
quotations, of folks said to endorse it—Davidson and Michael Smith,
but also Helen Steward, Adrian Haddock, John McDowell, and Brian
O'Shaughnessy. The point of such a list is, in a way, rhetorical: it
says, look, this isn't just Davidson and Davidsonians (*ahem*, no
matter what one might gather from the actually following text …): it's
pervasive in modern action theory. It's a deep tendency. One wants to
swell the ranks. (In this light including O'Shaughnessy is kind of
strange, actually, at least if my suspicion that he isn't much read
is correct.) That this is accomplished by corralling lots of short
quotations from the above-named persons, which evince what are
superficially similar positions, is somewhat astounding, since Ford
doesn't actually establish that they are the same position, which
would require expounding on each in context. The fact that two
philosophers summing up their positions in a few sentences might use
similar formulations no more establishes that their positions are
consonant than the fact that O'Shaughnessy and a probate proceeding
are both concerned with "the will" establishes that they have the same
topic. If the philosophers in question all came from broadly the same
school or lineage it might be fine, but Ford's whole point is that
they don't; we ought to be wary of casual syncretism.
Let us roughly group what follows thus: (a), why the inclusion of
O'Shaughnessy is prima facie puzzling (there are actually lots of
reasons for this, and I've only included the one that first came to
me, as I was reading Ford's paper); (b), why, on the other hand, one
might be tempted to include him, and what Ford quotes by way of
supporting this inclusion; (c), the connection of this to other
parts of the paper; (d), a look at the overall argumentative
structure of the paper; it's even less specific to O'Shaughnessy than
(c) is but there's something notably weird about it. Finally,
there are scads of notes, including two long ones that almost
constitute a rare thing from me, a defense of Davidson. We will begin,
conventionally, with (a).
(a) It's been a while since I read The Will, but I remember bits
of it well enough to be able to say that even before getting to the
quotation brought in to justify the identification of O'Shaughnessy as
a corporealist, one ought to find the mere fact of his inclusion
strange. For he does not merely fail to join the chorus of those
apologizing for their strange views with reference to the accordion
effect, he explicitly mentions it to say that it's bosh—he considers
at length the case of someone adjusting a radio's volume by
adjusting its volume knob (by moving his fingers), and whether one
ought to say, when speaking properly, that really he's only moving his
fingers, and the rest is simply an effect, and concludes that … one
should not say that. (Nor does he identify any point at which one
would be correct to say: here is the point at which the agent's
contribution stops.) So he not only does not do what we are told that
corporealists uniformly do, he seems to be rejecting corporealism in
one part of his (admittedly, long and complex) text, something that
ought to make us demand more than simply a single quotation with no
further explication to justify his inclusion in the corporealist body.
O'Shaughnessy even expresses himself, in the course of this
discussion, with prose that any Thompson epigone ought to admire:
Now the peculiar thing about the utterance, "He is really only
moving his fingers", is the word "only". What is it that is being
ruled out? What is it that he does not do? A strange and primitive
sort of linguistic reaction wells up within one at this stage. What
is it that he does not do? "Why, he doesn't do that", we say,
pointing at the movement of the knob that he is moving, "He isn't
doing that", pointing to the moving and glowing insides of the
wireless, "He isn't doing the causal connections!" This is a
bizarre and wild outbreak of the philosophical unconscious. (The
Will, 2nd ed, 109)
On p 108 he says outright that (supposing the radio is actually
working, the knob not jammed, etc.) "he is really only moving his
fingers" is "false". The discussion is quite lengthy and proceeds
somewhat eccentrically (his immediate concern is not Ford's, or
Davidson's), but I find nothing in it to undermine my initial seeming
recollection that O'Shaughnessy does not believe that action, strictly
aspeaking, extends only to bodily movements, or indeed to less than
what happens, much less only to willings in some bad merely internal
sense (O'Shaughnessy's own sense of "willing" is of course more
complicated than that), and plenty to support it, such as, say, "In
section (e) … I shall indicate what a valid motive for such a
restriction on the extension of 'action' might be, and show that no
such justification here exists" (117). Seems pretty unambiguous, if
merely promised (but I'm reading it through again in order, and don't
have all day, you know [1]).
(b) I'm not going to attempt to summarize the third chapter of the
first volume of The Will (since it really is about that much, if not
that and the second chapter for context, that's relevant to
O'Shaughnessy's consideration of the whether sensu stricto one only
ever moves one's body), but I do think this ought to suffice to show
that prima facie he's an odd choice to name as a corporealist,
underspecified as that position is, and Ford does very little to
support his inclusion. Nevertheless one must admit that statements
such as "once that outbreak [of the philosophical unconscious] is
fully analysed, we shall then find ourselves in a position to use the
once metaphysical 'I cannot move the knob of the wireless'
non-metaphysically. Analysing such a metaphysical utterance is the
very complicated process of giving it a use." (121–2) as, well, they
might make one think that in the end we will end up restricting
actions, in some sense, to bodily movements (always excepting, as
O'Shaughnessy does explicitly mention, actions that essentially
involve no gross movement) after all. And indeed the entire second
part of the first volume is concerned with "The Immediate Object of
the Will", namely, as it turns out, the body. (The modifier,
obviously, is important.)
It's not that, however, which Ford adduces, but this sentence
(-fragment, in context), which is, I think, somewhat less than
dispositive, even taken by itself, and much less than dispositive in
its larger context:
the event of willing physically develops, in a naturally appointed
causal manner, to the point at which it incorporates the event of
limb movement, and completes itself in so doing. (512)
I think it is reasonable to say that this does not precisely imply
that all we ever do, sensu stricto, is move our bodies, or that all
that happens after the movement (or some other thing) is technically
not our doing. For one thing, when I turn the volume knob, the (event
of the) turning takes place simultaneously with (the event of) my
fingers' moving! The event in which the willing completes itself, the
event of the bodily movement, and the event of the moving of the thing
moved by the body's moving can all be the same event. (And "willing"
is a technical term for O'Shaughnessy; one oughtn't just drop it into
one's piece as if its meaning is clear to all and move on.) And yet
this may be thought a rather special case; when the sharp pockets the
eight ball, or when Rube Goldberg operates his light switches, the
body's movement ends before the goal is attained. (On the other hand,
it might be thought that Ford's examples of transaction, too, are much
more like turning the radio knob than like what Rube
characteristically does, in that one is continually interacting with
the material on which one is acting.) So something is, if not
fishy precisely, in need of explanation; is all our willing really
exhausted in bodily movements?
It is somewhat tempting to observe that O'Shaughnessy's official remit
in the section in which that quotation occurs is "bodily action", and
so he may simply be concerned with actions that are no more than,
i.e. not more extended than, bodily movements (though he does also
refer to turnings on of lights). And I think he really is concerned,
here, mostly with basic actions (a concept he countenances, as do I),
because I think he is, here, concerned with wondering about, well, the
curious yet oh so classic duality seemingly exhibited by action
(psychic phenomena, yet also physical phenomena!), and the marriage of
mind and body exhibited in intentional bodily movements would seem to
be the place in which that problematic is exhibited in exemplary
fashion (this is a person, after all, who wrote a paper called "Trying
(As the Mental 'Pineal Gland')" and repeats the pineal gland line
again in The Will). There is something to be investigated about the
will and the body—about willings and movings—which is different from
the investigation of whether it is proper to identify action with
bodily movement.
Now it is from the late discussions explicitly about action (the first
part, that I was quoting from in (a), is not about action as such)
clear that O'Shaughnessy also countenances non-basic, instrumental or
constitutive actions, though unfortunately giving examples of his
doing so is made more difficult by the fact that he also countenances
the concept of the unintentional action, so when he speaks of starting
an avalanche by firing a rifle (as on 458; N.B., though, not "by
contracting a finger" on a trigger that happens to be hard by!), he
means this to be an unintentional doing. It ought to be borne in
mind that accepting the idea of a basic action, and holding the
position that ultimately everything one does one does by or in doing
basic actions (singly or in series), does not force one to hold the
further position that those basic actions qua intentional actions
are bodily movements in the way Davidson seems to intend; that is,
such a person can (and should!) fully adopt Ford's points on pp 707f.
(But then, as far as I can tell, so also can and should Davidson.)
(Such a person should also adopt my points in "Second Nature and
Basic Action"!) That is, one might analyze the structure of actions
into the instrumental/constitutive and the basic, such that all of the
former are accomplished (in some way) by or in the latter, without
committing oneself to identifying action with bodily movement, or
believing that the effects of the basic actions are not properly our
doings.
For all that, though, O'Shaughnessy especially in the second volume of
The Will, and especially its latter portions, does seem awfully
preoccupied, when talking about both action and the will, with bodily
movements, in a way that might lead one to think that that really is
all he thinks action amounts to. And it's not clear to me in this
paper but it seems at times as if for Ford recognizing basic actions
makes you a corporealist.
(c) As alluded to at the beginning of the post, there's a rather wide
range of positions that get put together as "corporealism" or that
count as "identifying action with bodily movement", and it's not
always super clear what it's intended to be captured. It doesn't help,
of course, that his leading target, Davidson, is monumentally unclear
about how to construe his position, in two ways. I suspect it's at
least correct that Davidson thinks that all our primitive or basic
actions are bodily movements, and that he thinks all our basic
actions are bodily movements under bodily-movement descriptions
(though the argument he advances, if that really his supposed to be
the position, is notably bad). The second thing there is in my opinion
incorrect and as far as I can tell comes in with no clear motivation
other than Davidson's apparent belief that it's theoretically neat; at
any rate, even saying that much doesn't amount to the claim, which of
course Davidson also makes, that all we do is move our bodies
(regardless of the description qua which these movements are
intentional actions), and when he adds that, he seems to be
contradicting himself [2]! (It still seems unfair of Ford to saddle
him with the charges that he doesn't believe in instrumental action or
that for him the body has no need of the extra-bodily [3].) But then
he's got Feinberg as a target, too, and Feinberg explicitly does not
believe that "all the actions there are" are bodily movements.
Ford characterizes both corporealism and voluntarism as species of
"practical dualism", and says that such a doctrine in general
divides what is presumed to be an unproblematic case of intentional
action, like turning on the lights, into two causally-related
[sic] parts, one of which is the agent's contribution to what
happens, and the other of which is "up to nature". Although I have
said that materialism marks no such division, the suspicion may
linger that it must do so, on pain of embracing an absurd
triumphalism, according to which there are no limits to what one can
do intentionally. (712)
It's almost like Frankfurt's concern in "The Problem of Action", but
his solution is (in my memory of it, anyway), a cybernetic
more-of-the-same. (And one ought to allow, in some circumstances, that
the agent is doing whatever she's doing even if she isn't following
the unfolding progress, ready to intervene, pace Frankfurt.)
I've quoted his remark about materialism and triumphalism as well
because I find the characterization of why someone actually would
want to speak of leaving something "up to nature" rather
confusing—what the temptation actually is, or, otherwise put, what
leaving something up to nature is supposed to mean. (That is, I'm not
sure what limits Ford thinks might be lifted in triumph. We would be
able to … turn on lights? Glow like filaments?) Why would someone
think that? What sort of not-doing might be in question in the "part"
that's up to nature? Surely there's an innocuous sense in which, once
I have poured the poison into the king's ear, I allow its its fatal
action of, I don't know, its binding to red blood cells and preventing
them from carrying oxygen, a natural potential which we exploit, to
run its course? Must saying that mean saying that I didn't kill the
king, I merely tilted my wrist just so? Whence the temptation to make
a special place for the body? What even is a body, anyway?
There is a strange missed opportunity early on in the introduction of
"materialism" as a term:
It did not escape [Aristotle's] notice that a person needs to move
herself in order to move something else. Nor did he fail to
appreciate that when one moves a stone by pushing it with a stick,
there are real and important differences between the "moving" one
does of the stone, the "moving" one does of the stick, and the
"moving" one does of oneself. But none of this led him to fixate on
the movement of the body. (700)
Unfortunately for me, Ford does not record where Aristotle notices
this [4]. Unfortunately for all of us, he doesn't record what those
important differences are, or again in the paper take cognizance of
fact that one must move oneself in order to move one's body, or what
the significance for the philosophy of action that fact might have. We
can take this, however, at least implicitly allowing that one can be a
materialist in good standing while affirming that bodily movements are
special, being both necessary for and different (in some important
way!) from the movements of the non-bodily.
In a footnote, he does tell us that the materialist tradition includes
Marx and many phenomenologists, adding that
one striking difference between phenomenologists, on the one hand,
and analytic action theorists, on the other, is that the former are
apt to devote while chapters of their main works to thinking about
the human body. There is nothing remotely similar in the Davidsonian
corpus. And that is the great irony of what I am calling
"corporealism": though analytic action theorists constantly mention
"bodily movement", the nature of the human body is rarely thematized
as a topic of philosophical reflection. (718n28)
Reader, I found this infuriating: O'Shaughnessy not only devotes a
whole hell of a lot of The Will precisely to the human body, much of
what he says resounds harmoniously with Merleau-Ponty. (Ford says next
to nothing about it.) It's especially irksome given that Ford spends
more time with this remark of Anscombe's, not obviously consonant with
Aristotle's noticing:
People sometimes say that one can get one's arm to move by an act of
will but not a matchbox; but if they mean 'Will a matchbox to move
and it won't' the answer is 'If I will my arm to move in that way,
it won't', and if they mean, 'I can move my arm but not my matchbox'
the answer is that I can move the matchbox—nothing easier.
(quoted on 706)
This seems to lose track of the idea that there is a real, much less
an important, difference between the two movings. Something seems to
have escaped Anscombe's notice, at least in the use Ford makes of this
remark. What, after all, is the way in which I move my arm, when I
move it to move the matchbox? And if I try—do I even know how to
try?—to move the matchbox that way, do I? It's in the context of
O'Shaughnessy's lengthy considerations of, basically, just this
question that he first disputes that we only ever do the
finger-moving, and not also the volume adjusting, but this doesn't
lead him to gloss over the differences between the two. (It is bizarre
of Ford to commend Aristotle for not "fixating" on the body and, in a
footnote attached to just that commendation, commend phenomenologists
for (and abuse analytic philosophers for not) occupying themselves
deeply with the body. As we know, a "fixation" is a theory, or an
object of study eventuating in a theory, one doesn't like.) If we
retain notice of the necessity of moving oneself in order to move
something else, then there must surely be a sense in which one can
move oneself but not the matchbox: one doesn't move the matchbox in
the way one moves oneself, or one wouldn't need to move oneself in
order to move the matchbox. (Or the matchbox would be oneself, which
is not a priori impossible.) Thus while I don't know what parts of
Aristotle Ford had in his mind, what came first to mine was this:
It follows that the soul is analogous to the hand; for as the hand
is a tool of tools, so the mind is the form of forms and sense the
form of sensible things. (DA 432a)
Much could be made about the perception/action parallel being drawn in
these few lines with respect to the instant problematic [5], but it
flashed on me because, well, isn't it odd that we should even have a
tool of tools? Like, we've got all these tools, right, both artifacts
made (often using other tools!) for our purposes, and natural objects
appropriated as-is to be used for this or that. Why don't we just use
them? Why don't we use the tools, that is, directly, rather than
using a tool of tools to use them? (And if for some reason we must use
a tool of tools to use the tools, why mustn't we use a tool of tools
of tools to use the tool of tools?) Haven't we, after all, just been
assured that we can do precisely that, namely just use the (say)
knife to peel the apple—nothing easier?
Well, the answer is, you can indeed peel an apple, but try to peel an
apple that way, and you won't. For that matter, you can indeed move
your spleen, but try to move it that way, and you won't. For
O'Shaughnessy, as indeed for Merleau-Ponty, the "body" with which we
are concerned does not include the spleen, but does, or at least
can, include such incorporeal addenda as prosthetics (O'S) or canes
(M-P) [6]. (This is another thing that, all by itself, ought to give
one pause before including O'Shaughnessy among the corporealists!)
Such things are, for those who have learned how to use them, among the
"immediate object[s] of the will", in O'Shaughnessy's phrase. I don't
think "object" is the happiest term, or necessary for him, since it
implies that the will acts on the body and the body, then, on
something else; the point is the immediacy, which we do not enjoy
(except if we have, as he puts it, "rare powers") with respect to
knives.
One is tempted to say something like this: we need a tool of tools
because the active powers of the soul do not extend directly to all
the world, as infants are said to believe they do; we are finite
beings whose practical efficacy requires physical intercession, and
physical intercession in the world happens via the soul's physical
expression, which is the body. (Ronald Polansky, in his commentary on
De anima, puts it by saying "the hand reaches out to touch and grasp
many things, while the soul through its cognitive faculties embraces
the whole world of things" (496), which nicely sets up the hand not
merely as like the soul or the soul as like the hand but the hand as
the active counterpart to the soul's receptive nature.) And this is
also why we do not need a tool of tools of tools: the body is the
actualization of our active nature, not a tool which the soul makes
use of (though it's not always easy to find the right way to express
this thought). This poses no particular restriction on what counts as
"the body" (it could include canes; it could exclude spleens; it is
apt to be different for you and for me) or the range of activities in
which our practical natures are immediately (or mediately) expressed.
Whether this amounts to identifying actions with bodily movements is
unclear; the "body" in question is not the biological body, and we
have no reason not to say that the laces, when I tie them, are
temporarily incorporated, to a limited purpose. (If we do this, we do
so because the laces figure in the sole or most basic practical
thought involved in lace-tying; we have lost grasp of "the body"
independent from that in which the will expresses itself practically.
Actually I think what to say about things not connected to the body
that nevertheless figure in the most basic practical thought, like the
cup one goes to grasp and to whose outline one's hand is conformed in
anticipation, is a super interesting question, but I don't really have
a settled opinion about it.) This is if not a distinct "part" at least
relevantly different from what we accomplish in and/or by thus
expressing ourselves, in that those further things we do are, well,
again, being finite, we are dependent on, uh, nature and natural
regularities to effect our desires. "Up to nature" gives the whole
thing a rather helpless air, which Ford, with his previous rather
unaccountable invocation of "luck", makes much of:
The dualist's conviction that an agent must leave something up to
nature, even when all she is doing is turning on the lights, betrays
an unrealistic conception of the ordinary objects that we use on a
daily basis … the only "nature" in question is an incandescent light
bulb … they are made by human beings to be used by human beings … it
is no accident that they tend to turn on when people flip the
switches that are made to turn them on. (713)
Ford doesn't say what the unrealistic conception actually is! (Does he
think that it means, like, the woods? I honestly found this baffling.)
Presumably, though, on it, it is an accident that light bulbs mostly
do turn on when their switches are flipped. This only makes sense if
"the rest is up to nature" means "sure, I flipped the switch, and it's
anybody's guess what happens next", or something like that; but—whence
might he have gotten that idea? [7] It is precisely because leaving
things up to nature is not a matter of accident that we can make
light bulbs at all; I can leave it up to the filament to glow when the
current goes through it. Indeed, I don't need to know anything about
the construction of light bulbs or the wiring of my home to operate a
light switch. I just flip the switch! The rest—lovely nature—takes
care of itself, and need not be represented in my practical or indeed
theoretical thought at all [8]. The temptation to speak of leaving
stuff up to nature is not, I think, that otherwise we seem to be
omnipotent, but the simple observation that I just loose the string
and the arrow goes, flip the switch and the light turns on, pour the
poison and the king dies, rub the sticks and the kindling lights,
whatever, there's the thing I'm immediately doing, and the things that
I do by so doing. (Ford wants to say that "when I intentionally turn
on the lights, what I change intentionally is not merely the switch
that I manipulate, but [also] the lights" (713). So does
O'Shaughnessy, and, for that matter, so does Davidson. Ford's own
formulation acknowledges that one manipulates the switch, but not the
lights. How do the lights come to be light, rather than dark, then? Is
it because the manipulation closes a circuit, which sends electricity
through the filament, which causes the filament to get really hot and
emit light? If so, is it merely by courtesy that we say that I changed
the lights intentionally?) And although I need to rub my hands on the
stick up here so that the other end down there turns in the wood, it
is in the nature of the wood down there to be heated and ignite from
the friction. I am turning, heating, igniting; but I am relying on
nature to get me from deed to deed.
One is tempted to believe that in so saying one is not sinning against
materialism, or at least falling into corporealism, and that
O'Shaughnessy can safely be said to have evaded the charge. It seems,
where it skirts territory Ford anathematizes, to be doing so
innocuously, in unmetaphysical ways, and it seems to be drawing out
the primacy and difference of bodily movement which he seems to
tolerate in Aristotle. But I'm not certain, because Ford has McDowell
in the beginning saying precisely that
"actualizations of our active nature" extend into the "goings-on in
which natural things, like limbs, do natural things, like moving."
For McDowell, it is things like hands, not things like handles,
whose movements are realizations of our "active nature". The mind
enters the world, he thinks, but only a little way[.] (698)
So, who knows! I mean, hands and not handles seems right up there with
tools of tools and not tools. But I still think that O'Shaughnessy is
being miscategorized. I certainly think that the diversity of
positions putatively under consideration, relative to the attention
given to any actual position, is unfortunate: it really does seem
unclear to me whether assenting to "there are basic actions" is
supposed to make one a corporealist. I don't think it does?
(d) Here's the overall structure of the paper: volitionalism asserts
its primacy on the grounds of three considerations (which I will call
"the first three"): fallibility (of bodily movement as against
willing), separability (of willing from movement), and etiology (of
bodily movement from willing). Against these corporealism asserts it
has the advantage with another three considerations ("the second
three"): pre-theoretical practical thought, embodiment, and animality.
Things can't just stand there, though; corporealism has to address
the first three. Ford gives it two options: deny the phenomena (an
option he says is "rarely, if ever, exercised", possibly because of
"its lack of promise" (705)) or to "grant the phenomena, but deny that
they disqualify bodily movement as the prime expression of agency"
(705).
However, materialism now comes along and says: just as the second
three give corporealism the edge over volitionalism, so too they give
materialism the edge over corporealism: if you find those
considerations moving, you should be moved to materialism. Against
that, corporealism advances counter-considerations against
materialism: fallibility (of transaction as against bodily movement),
separability (of bodily movement from transaction), and etiology (of
transaction from movement). But wait—didn't the corporealist just say
that those considerations have no force?
Ford says yes—the corporealist did just say that, and is therefore
"in the impossible position of needing to deny out of one side of
their mouths … exactly what they affirm out of the other that
fallibility, separability and etiological priority establish the
primacy of one expression of agency as against another" (711).
What's weird about this is: Ford is a person who likes to reject
highest-common-factor type considerations. You know the sort of thing:
formally, or from one limited perspective, these two things are the
same, and so, we're stuck. He seems to envision the only possible
route the corporealist could take against the volitionalist as being:
"no consideration of separability ever favors any one conception of
agency over any other". It's just not, formally, the sort of
consideration that could do that. And yet, isn't there another
possibility? Couldn't there be a substantive argument against the
specific consideration, in which the corporealist simply says "this
consideration of separability, for substantive reasons pertaining to
(say) the nature of willing, or of tryings, or bodily movings, or
whatever, doesn't favor volitionalism over corporealism"? (George
Wilson—and I, in the second chapter of my dissertation!—have made
arguments against "pure intending", for instance. As has, in a
different vein, Thompson, I believe.)
It's possible that doing this would amount, in Ford's view, to denying
the phenomena, because it disputes their characterization. (But it
might only dispute their significance, but specifically with respect
to their natures: accept the phenomena, deny the "thus …", but not
because the genre of consideration is wrong.) If so, though, I don't
know why he just says without expanding on it that the strategy lacks
promise or is hardly ever undertaken: it seems promising to me, and he
literally quotes O'Shaughnessy in the process of, if not undertaking
specifically that project, at least developing a position from which
to undertake it (717n14). Of course I've been denying that
O'Shaughnessy is a corporealist, but Ford seems to be saying that it's
not done by and not promising for anyone.
Similarly, corporealism could deny that the considerations it
supposedly adduces against volitionalism do in fact move one all the
way to materialism. For instance, consider pre-theoretical practical
thought, and Rube Goldberg machines for turning lights on. I set one
off by putting a teakettle to boil, and five minutes later a domino,
pushed over by its rear neighbor, is pushing its fore neighbor over. I
think that if you zoom in, as it were, just on that, pre-theoretical
practical thought would be willing to say, well, you aren't doing
that. (Pre-theoretical practical thought is not unrelated to
O'Shaughnessy's philosophical unconscious! At the same time it
probably would say I'm turning the light on, but the whole thing about
the pre-theoretical is that one has to allow it to be not obviously
systematic or self-consistent.) You just started it off, P-TPT might,
quite plausibly, say. Feinberg looks pretty good on this score, if you
ask me! (Ford's own discussion of how P-TPT approaches the
corporealism-materialism divide is extremely theoretical.)
ETA on the following day: of course basic actions probably do suffice to make one a corporealist on this view, given the (only now clear to me) strong family resemblance between Ford's characterization here, and Lavin's, in "Must There Be Basic Action?", of the basic agent as one who as it were supervises the unfolding but does not participate in it as agent. But this is only a resemblance of characterization; it isn't support for the inclusion, and as we know (don't we, loyal audience of readers?) I think Lavin has things badly wrong about basic action.
[1] This is a joke, of course; this was written in far more than a day, and has involved reading far more
of The Will (and of other things) than I initially predicted it might. But I'm leaving these first two parts sketchy.
[2] Specifically, he writes:
It is correctly assumed that unless the agent himself is aware of
what he is doing with his body alone, unless he can conceive his
movements as an event physically separate from whatever else takes
place, his bodily movements cannot be his action. But it is wrongly
supposed that such awareness and conception are impossible in the
case of speaking or of tying one's shoelaces … if I tie my
shoelaces, here is a description of my movements: I move my body in
just the way required to tie my shoelaces. ("Agency", 51)
Ok, fine. But there's a big difference between "the agent is aware"
and "it's not impossible for the agent to be aware"! Sure, the agent
could aware of his movements under the anodyne description, but
mostly, the agent is not, or if the agent is, it's in a derived,
theoretical way. And when it is, it's in a derived practical way: I
want to demonstrate how I move when I tie my shoelaces, and I know
that I will move in that way if I tie my shoelaces, so I tie them. But
here the syllogism is "I want to move however I move when I tie my
laces; if I tie my laces I will do that; so: let me tie my laces".
It's not the other way around! (It's interesting that Thompson and
Lavin make this exact error when they argue against basic actions. The
deep Davidsonian core of Pittsburgh Anscombianism!) But perhaps
Davidson merely means: something like this has to be the case for my
bodily movements not to be foreign to me; not: when I tie my shoelaces
I move my hands under this description. One might say, for instance,
that it's correctly supposed that unless beliefs can be adduced which
display one's movements in a rational light and which the one would
accept they cannot be one's actions, and point out that when one steps
through a door without first checking what's on the far side obviously
one believed that there was a floor there. That doesn't mean that one
explicitly thought "there's a floor there, so I can step". One's
bodily movements aren't foreign to one when tying one's laces
because one can recognize them as one's own under a laces-inclusive
description, might be the thought. Of course this doesn't lead to the
conclusion that only bodily movements are actions, but neither does
it exclude it. I think there just isn't a good reason to be found in
"Agency" for restricting basic action to bodily movement! (AFAICT, and
again this isn't coming from a careful re-reading, the structure is
basically "here's an idea" followed by "here are responses to some
objections". Ok, but how about a positive argument?)
The apparent contradiction lies in the juxtaposition of "once he has
done one thing … each consequence presents us with a deed" (53), some
of which are intentional (that is, as I would say, the one thing
presents us with further actions) with bodily movements being "all the
actions there are" (59), unless there's some extremely subtle
distinction between "action" and "intentional deed". It's especially
bad if the movements are intentional only under movement descriptions,
because then one can't appeal as easily to the movements having been
done for the sake of the further consequences, and because on 53
Davidson seems to be saying that the intention with which the body is
moved is relevant to which of the further consequences are
intentional, which is hard to make out unless the description is not
cast solely in bodily terms. But I don't think we need to think that
they are, even on Davidson's own terms. (It's really unclear to me why
Davidson says that, about "all the actions there are". What would be
lost to him if he just said "all primitive actions are bodily
movements" and left it at that? For that matter, what would be lost to
him if he just said "there is some set of primitive actions"? Not
much, I suspect, especially in the first case.)
[3] Thus:
[T]hey do not need [the extra-corporeal] to state their position on
the only other kind of action, non-primitive action, since there
position is, in fact, purely hypothetical: … if the agent's bodily
movement causes a further event, then the latter is also the
agent's doing … the kind of "body" that corporealism attributes to
us is one whose activity does not essentially involve any
interaction with the extra-corporeal world … But the movement proper
to a human body, and therefore to a human being, essentially
involves extra-corporeal objects. (709)
(It's interesting to note, perhaps, that O'Shaughnessy also observes
that someone who thinks that we only ever move our bodies is in danger
of denying the existence of instrumental acts (109).) This impression
is made more vivid by Ford's rather tendentious characterization of
how the downstream effects get in the picture: they do so "given the
right setting and a certain amount of luck" (697), as if people were
in the habit of flicking their fingers and hoping that a light switch
that might just be connected to a light in this very room might be
nearby. Davidson of course says instead that "the rest is up to
nature" (Agency, 59), a rather more defensible and much different
claim (nature is the realm of laws, not of luck!), if one that does
smack of the outbreak of the philosophical unconscious O'Shaughnessy
notes: he isn't (pointing at the wire leading to the light bulb) doing
the conductivity of copper! He isn't (pointing at the filament)
doing the emission of photons!
The diagnosis about instrumentality would have surprised Davidson, who
supplies a clear case of instrumental action two sentences after
making the claim Ford disputes:
First, it will be said that some actions require that we do others
in order to bring them off, and so cannot be primitive: for example,
before I can hit the bull's eye, I must load and raise my gun, then
aim and pull the trigger. Of course I do not deny that we must
prepare the way for some actions by performing others. (Agency,
59)
I load the gun in order to later hit the bull's eye. It won't do to
insist, against this, that really all I do is perform a variety of
bodily movements among whose effects is the loading of the gun, unless
we are also forestalled from saying that those bodily movements are
done in order to later make it the case that my contracting of my
finger causes a bullet, rather than nothing at all, to fly out of the
barrel. As for the idea that the bodily movements presupposed by
corporealism make no reference to the extra-corporeal, that too would
have surprised Davidson, was worse off than being unable to describe
or think how he moves his fingers when he ties his laces: "nor am I
capable of moving my fingers in the appropriate way when no laces are
present (this is a trick I might learn)" (Agency, 51—this comes
immediately after a bit Ford quotes). It sure seems as if Davidson
thinks that in order for him to be able perform this bodily movement,
something extra-bodily has to be to hand. (So to speak.) It also has
to be present to thought, because the practical thought Davidson gins
up to solve the problem he thinks confronts him, if in fact it is
supposed to be a practical thought, is to move his body however it
moves to tie his shoelaces. (And why would I do that if not to tie
my shoelaces?)
To be sure: "it would have surprised Davidson" doesn't mean the
accusation is unjust. But I think it does mean that one ought to
support the accusation, either directly or with a reference. What's
worse is that Ford isn't really accusing Davidson alone of these
things; it's supposed to be a common failing of all corporealists. But
this is even harder to substantiate, for even if we believe that
philosophers with a great diversity of backgrounds have all converged
on something that can be thus characterized, that doesn't mean
they've all converged on the same something, and making the charges
stick in each case might require considering the details of the
particular somethings in question. Or it might not: but Ford doesn't
do much to convince us that the common position, if there is a single
position, can in virtue solely of what is common be convicted of the
charges.
[4] Perhaps this is just super obvious to those in the swim, on a
level with not providing a citation for something about the virtues
being a mean.
[5] Ford draws the obvious (given the author) general parallel, that
rejecting practical dualism is like rejecting the thesis that all one
perceives is sense data. O'Shaughnessy also brings perception into the
mix (456–8) (he retains the sense datum, but holds that
perceiving it is identical with perceiving the thing; that is, there's
no inferential leap—odd position but not the concern here).
[6] If I remember correctly, Merleau-Ponty is willing to expand this
to automobiles!
[7] I suspect that regarding causalists one actually can make
something like this argument go, at least a little, but that requires
making the argument specifically about causalists, which, again, is
not Ford's ambition.
[8] Here's an ultra-pedantic quibble, but then, claims of necessity
ought to be subject to pedantry:
If, as Anscombe claims, "the failure to execute intentions is
necessarily the rare exception," then, since we normally use
instruments to execute our intentions, our instruments must normally
serve the purposes that we put them to.
#Actually, we can be more reliable in executing our intentions than
our instruments are in serving our purposes. For a silly example,
consider the esoteric programming language
Java2k:
Because (almost) all builtin functions in Java2K have only a 90%
chance of returning the correct result, actual results often deviate
more-or-less from expected results. So, the real challenge is to
develop techniques of getting a higher probability of correct
results !
It is relatively easy to write a function that will return a one 90%
of the time, but it is more difficult to write a function that has a
99.9999% chance of doing so, and even more difficult of doing this
to a function that returns something as simple as the number two.
More difficult but not impossible. Or consider this task: given a
biased coin that shows heads 2/3 of the time, flip it and get tails.
The technique is simple: just keep doing it until you get tails.
But, if our instruments do normally serve our purposes, it's because
nature … is … reliable?
Recent Comments